About five months ago I put two Royal Copenhagen “Christmas at Niagara Falls” plates up for sale on Kijiji on behalf of my upstairs neighbour, David. I started them out at $40 each, after two months took $10 off and two months later I knocked the price down to $20. On Monday I finally got a call from a collector in Niagara that wanted to come into town on Tuesday and buy them. It turns out he graduated from OCA in 1980, three years before I started working there. He’s also one of the last people in the world that only has a land-line and he can’t call me when he arrives, so I’ll have to meet him in the donut shop.
I
spent most of the day working on my Philosophy essay. Here’s a bit of what I
have so far:
Anselm’s Monologian attempts to prove the existence
of god by presenting qualities that human beings value, such as goodness and
greatness. He then elevates each of these qualities to their comparative
adjectives, “better” and “greater” in order to show that every quality we
recognize can have a purer manifestation. He concludes that each value must
have a superlative, as in “best” and “greatest” at a plateau that he considers
not only to be the utmost manifestation of these qualities, but also their source,
or god, which he insists is the meeting place of all superlatives and
the source of all existence, and which must necessarily be the source of its
own existence.
He presents these
qualities as what we have in common with each other, the rest of creation and
ultimately with god. Of one quality, he says that we all share a common
goodness. Goodness for Anselm is not thought in terms of behaviour, as in
children being good boys and girls. He relates the assessment of comparative
goodness with the degree to which something is useful, as in his example of a
horse being good through its strength or its speed. He asserts that a human
being better than a horse and does not venture to prove this point, but
certainly if goodness is equated with degree of utility it would not be
difficult to conclude that in general a human has more utility and therefore
goodness than a horse or any other creature that is known to humanity.
Continuing with
Anselm’s equating of usefulness with goodness, since god, according to Anselm
is the superlative manifestation of goodness, although he does not specifically
refer to god as useful, it would be by Anselm’s definition the ultimate
utility. He does not in this text delineate the utilitarian relationship that
he thinks god has with humanity other than to be the source of all existence,
including the existence of the quality of goodness. The only way that he
presents the utility of goodness specifically in the Monologian is
through his example of a horse being good through either strength or speed. He
does however indicate by an inverted example how he understands usefulness in
human beings. He states that a fast and strong robber is not good because they
are harmful, which is the opposite of useful, but also the opposite of helpful
and so from this it can be concluded that a good human is also useful or
helpful and that the best human being would be the most useful or helpful.
Anselm does not speak of usefulness or harmfulness except in relation to human
beings being helped or harmed and this suggests that the goodness of things is
valued according to how useful they are to human beings. This would include
human beings being seen as good according to how useful or helpful they are to
each other.
But if usefulness
and goodness are synonymous in Anselm’s reckoning then how can human beings be
perceived as good by a self-existent superior being that is supposed to be the
source of all goodness? Of what use are human beings to an entity that is fully
self-supporting? If human beings are
not useful to god, then from god’s perspective human beings would have no
goodness.
Regarding Anselm’s
example of the horse, from the animal’s perspective, what is useful and
therefore good would not necessarily be the same as the utilitarian expectations
that humans have of horses. Speed and strength in a horse might very well be
useful both for humans as users of horses and for the well-being and survival
of horses in a herd. But other qualities that would be useful and therefore
good for horses may be detrimental to a horse’s utilitarian function and
therefore goodness for a human being. For example, a stallion that is not
intended for breeding is usually more useful to a user of horses if he is
gelded, because otherwise he will often be hard to control. But the qualities
that would make a horse difficult for a human to control would be useful and
therefore good for a horse in the wild.
Regarding Anselm’s
example of the fast and strong robber representing the opposite of goodness
because of harmfulness, the legend of Robin Hood, who robbed from the rich and
gave to the poor, comes to mind. There are also many cases in historical
conflicts in which stealing from the enemy is considered useful and therefore
good. But what is useful and good for one side in a war is almost always
harmful for the other side.
The fact that
there are conflicting goodnesses contradicts Anselm’s claim that there is a
common goodness in nature with only differences of degree and level that has
its source in the goodness of god. If
there truly is a commonality of goodness in all things, it could not be
discerned by utility.
It
is not clear why Anselm accepts the concept of a supreme being going on forever
as more plausible than an infinite procession of succeeding superior manifestations
of these qualities.